Is Taxation Theft | Teen Ink

Is Taxation Theft

December 28, 2023
By Anonymous

Introduction

Ancient Egyptian farmers, weary from a day's work in the blazing sun, reserve a portion of their grain harvest for the Pharaoh's tax collectors, a practice as routine as the rising Nile. This time-worn tradition from the riverbanks of Egypt was one of the earliest forms of taxation, a system that has evolved over millennia into the complex global frameworks we grapple with today. While the mechanisms of taxation have changed dramatically, the principle remains the same: the collection of revenue for public use.

It is this revenue that has fueled the progress of civilizations and societies, stitching together the tapestry of human advancement. However, it's a curious contradiction that for something so integral to our societal structure, taxes are often met with more dread than enthusiasm. If taxation is indeed the lifeblood of societal advancement, why does it provoke such strong disdain?

As we prepare to unpack this engaging conundrum of whether taxation is theft, we plan to use a unique trifocal lens to delve into our analysis. This essay will investigate the topic through the perspectives of utilitarianism, deontology, and legal positivism. These three ethical and philosophical theories provide comprehensive viewpoints, each with its own focus on outcomes, duty, and law, respectively. Looking at the issue of taxation through these varied lenses provides a broad view that appreciates the complexity of the subject, the nuances in its understanding, and helps facilitate a more informed conclusion. By adopting these three divergent but equally crucial perspectives, we aim to unravel their individual insights and collectively build a comprehensive understanding of the relationship between taxation and theft and conclude that taxation is indeed not theft.

Utilitarian Perspective

Utilitarianism, with its emphasis on the greatest good for the greatest number, allows us to assess the collective benefits of taxation. In evaluating taxation through the utilitarian lens, it is essential to recognize one of the underlying conditions of theft – the individual being stolen from ends up unambiguously worse off. However, when considering the construct of taxation, this condition does not always hold true.

For the average individual, the benefits derived from the taxes paid, from public infrastructure, education, healthcare, or safety, are likely to outweigh the initial financial costs (taxes paid). In other words, paying taxes can be seen as a type of communal investment. In this sense, the person isn't worse off but in fact better off due to the collective advantages made possible by taxation.

One could argue that this isn't always the case, particularly for high-income earners who pay a substantial sum in taxes. One could contend that these individuals may not receive benefits commensurate to their tax contribution. But even this viewpoint warrants a closer examination.

Those who accumulate significant wealth have often leveraged the opportunities and services that are funded by tax revenue. The stability and order of a functioning government, the infrastructure that facilitates commerce, public health measures that prevent widespread diseases, the educational institutions that foster talent and innovation, and even the protection of their wealth through law enforcement and the judiciary, all typically financed through taxation, contribute to creating an environment in which individuals can amass wealth. So while these individuals might pay more in absolute terms, they have previously reaped, and continue to reap, substantial benefits from a system financed by taxes.

Thus, a utilitarian analysis of taxation should not merely focus on the raw numbers of tax contribution but should take into account the overall benefit an individual derives from a tax-financed system. If the average individual, over a lifetime, receives more in benefits than they pay in taxes, it would be difficult to classify taxation as theft under a utilitarian framework. By this metric, not only does the individual not become worse off, but the wider society also benefits, marking a clear departure from the conventional understanding of theft.

Take government spending on public education as an example. In the 2019-20 school year, the total expenditure for public elementary and secondary schools in the United States was approximately $870 billion, or an average of $17,013 per student enrolled. Assuming an inflation rate of 3% per year and accounting for a 12-year basic education, the cumulative cost for an individual's public-school education would be approximately $240,000. In contrast, the average annual income of a high school graduate is around $34,000. Over a lifetime of 36 years (approximately 38 for men and 34 for women), accounting for 3% inflation, this amounts to $2.1 million in total earnings.  Based on these earnings, the average effective tax rate for this level of income is approximately 15% (U.S. federal tax and state tax). Therefore, this individual will generate $320,000 in taxes over 36 years.

When compared, the total tax contribution ($320,000) far exceeds the cost of public-school education ($240,000) for this individual. Therefore, even on this singular measure of public education, the high school graduate has received benefits that significantly outweigh their tax contributions. Of course, one could argue that the tax revenue is not solely used to pay for public education but rather for all public resources. However, one could also respond that the socioeconomic benefits of holding a job are much more than just the tax revenue generated, from stimulating economic activity and producing surplus utility to employers and consumers. Thus, this quantifiable example highlights how, on average, an individual can derive more value from tax-funded services than they contribute, thereby undermining the argument of taxation as theft under a utilitarian perspective.

Deontological Perspective

The realm of deontology, rooted in the Greek 'deon' denoting duty, houses a moral theory that prioritizes obligations and duties over the outcomes. Unlike utilitarianism, deontology focuses less on the consequences and more on the intent and the ethical dimensions of the action. Hence, it provides a distinct perspective to probe the question: Is taxation theft?

Let's consider one of the defining aspects of theft: it is considered an immoral act. From the deontological perspective, morality is defined by adherence to rules and duties. As such, whether taxation is deemed immoral or not largely depends on how we view the act of taxation. If it is perceived as a breach of property rights, then, indeed, taxation could be seen as theft. However, viewing taxation as an obligatory act, tied to our duty as members of society, we realize taxation isn't theft, but rather, a fulfillment of a civic duty.

The inviolability of personal property rights and the principle of non-aggression serve as the base of the argument that views taxation as theft. These principles uphold that forcibly taking someone's property is ethically wrong. Thus, given the obligatory nature of taxes, taxation could be seen as infringing upon these rights.

Yet, when we examine taxation according to the social contract theory—a concept central to many deontological theories—a counterpoint emerges. By living in a country and/or holding a country’s citizenship, we agree to abide by certain rules and regulations, which include the duty to pay taxes. Thus, rather than theft, taxation becomes a contractual obligation we undertake as citizens. For example, the 16th Amendment to the U.S. Constitution, which states, "The Congress shall have power to lay and collect taxes on incomes, from whatever source derived, without apportionment among the several States, and without regard to any census or enumeration."

A second condition of theft is that something is only considered stolen if the owner is unaware or hasn't given consent for forfeiture, which clearly is not the case with taxation. In democratic societies, citizens are aware of taxes and ostensibly consent to them via the election of representatives who institute tax laws. Even though paying taxes is compulsory, it can be viewed as arising from a form of initial consent, further distancing taxation from the concept of theft.

Beyond societal obligations, deontological ethics also consider moral duties. Paying taxes contributes to the common good by funding public services and goods. Hence, not paying taxes could be seen as a breach of this moral duty, further reinforcing that taxation is not theft, but a fulfillment of societal and moral obligations.

The argument can be made that deontology neglects potential misappropriation of tax revenue or perceived unfairness in certain tax laws. However, such criticisms can be addressed within a deontological framework, focusing on enhancing transparency, accountability, and fairness in tax policy and government spending, rather than invalidating the morality of taxation itself.

Thus, from a deontological perspective, taxation might seem like theft due to its violation of property rights. However, by considering the principles of the social contract, consent, and duty, taxation can be better understood as a moral obligation, not theft.

Legal Positivism

Legal positivism, a school of thought in jurisprudence, contends that a law's validity doesn't hinge on inherent morality, but rather on societal recognition and constructs. Here, it's the legality, not morality, of an action that carries weight, because society acknowledges the law, and government authority enforces it. This view resonates in the comparison between theft and taxation. Theft, a long-standing crime against property, is a covert, non-violent act that removes property from an individual without consent, usually intending illegal possession. In stark contrast, taxation is a legal obligation where the state collects a portion of national income to address societal needs. It's an appropriation carried out under public power and in full accordance with the law. Additionally, taxpayers are granted the right to know what tax they owe and how these funds are used. The two acts, though involving transfer of property, are distinctly differentiated by their legality - a perspective underscored by legal positivism.

Furthermore, the legitimacy of taxation is affirmed by its legal standing. Tax codes are enacted by legislatures, upheld by judicial and executive branches, forming a legal framework that mandates taxation. Examples of such legal frameworks exist across countries and eras, such as the U.S. Internal Revenue Code and the U.K. Finance Act. Since taxation is established in most legal systems worldwide, especially in democratic countries, underscores its legality and legitimacy.

However, a further question that may arise is, "If something is legal, can it still be considered theft?", but from the perspective of legal positivism, the answer is a simple no. Theft is an illegal act — if taxation is legal and enforced via a legally recognized process, it cannot be considered theft, regardless of any moral reservations.

Implicit consent forms a significant component of this argument. Citizens of democratic societies implicitly consent to abide by the laws established by their elected representatives. Thus, by participating in a democratic system, individuals provide tacit consent to the tax laws. This principle starkly differentiates taxation from acts of theft, which are non-consensual.

While some may argue that taxation aligns more with the concept of 'robbery' — a forcible seizure of property — it is important to consider the context. The state does use its power to enforce tax laws, and non-compliance can indeed lead to legal consequences. Yet, these consequences are part of the state's legal recourse and are widely recognized and accepted as part of the social and legal contract between the state and its citizens.

Thus, when viewed through the lens of legal positivism, taxation cannot be equated to theft. It's critical to differentiate personal moral judgments from societal legal constructs. Taxation is a legal requirement, authorized by our societal norms and democratic processes, which stands in stark contrast to the illicit act of theft.

Conclusion

Drawing insights from the diverse landscapes of utilitarianism, deontology, and legal positivism, we've navigated the complex terrain of the question: Is taxation theft? Utilitarianism illustrates the social harmony crafted by taxation, outweighing individual costs. Deontology highlights taxation as a civic responsibility, woven into the tapestry of societal obligations. Legal positivism firmly establishes taxation as a societal law, setting it apart from the illicit act of theft. Together, these perspectives harmonize into a resounding chorus: Taxation is not theft, but a fundamental underpinning of societal progress. This trifocal approach underscores the value of our shared fiscal responsibility in the symphony of civilization.



Similar Articles

JOIN THE DISCUSSION

This article has 0 comments.